Main Article Content

Authors

This article presents a reflection on the place and the relevance of the philosophy of art in an artworld in which anything can be a work of art, from the theoretical proposal of Arthur Danto. If the philosophy has something to say about art, it would be from a position that recognizes the centrality of the artistic practice without demarcating it. The opening in the art cannot be a matter of denial or trial, but an incentive to the thought. However, according to Danto, this requires to accept points of departure and consequences which alter the relationship between art and philosophy.

Pineda Repizzo, A. F. (2011). The Philosophy of Art at the Time of the End of Art. Praxis Filosófica, (32), 249–267. https://doi.org/10.25100/pfilosofica.v0i32.3446
CARROLL, Noël. (1998). “The end of art?”, History and theory, Vol.37/No.4 (Dec.), pp.17-29

CARROLL, Noël. (1995). “Avant-Garde art and the problem of theory”,Journal of aesthetic education, Vol.29/No.3 (Autumn), pp.1-13

CARROLL, Noël. (2001). “Modernity and the plasticity of perception”, Thejournal of aesthetics and art criticism, Vol.59/No.1 (Winter), pp.11-17

DANTO, Arthur. (1986). The philosophical disenfranchisement of art.NY, Columbia University Press

DANTO, Arthur. (1999). “Indiscernibility and perception: a reply to JosephMargolis”, British journal of aesthetics, Vol.39/No.4 (Oct.), pp.321-329

DANTO, Arthur. (1999b). Después del fin del arte. Barcelona, Paidos.

DANTO, Arthur. (2002). La transfiguración del lugar común. Barcelona,Paidós.

DANTO, Arthur. (2003). Más allá de la Caja Brillo. Madrid, Akal.

DANTO, Arthur. (2005). El abuso de la belleza. Barcelona, Paidós.

DAVIES, Stephen. (1991). Definitions of art. NY, Cornell University Press.

DAVIES, Stephen. & Stecker, Robert. (2009). “Twentieth-century Anglo-American aesthetics”, en: Stephen Davies et alt, A companion to aesthetics,Oxford, Blackwell Publishing.

DAVIES, Stephen. & Stecker, Robert. (1997). The art circle. Chicago, Chicago Spectrum Press

DICKIE, George. (2001). Art and Value. Massachusetts, BlackwellPublishers.

DUCHAMP, Marcel. (1978). Escritos. Duchamp du signe. Barcelona,Gustavo Gili.

GOODMAN, Nelson. (1968). Languages of art. Indianapolis, The Bobbs-Merrill Company

HEGEL, G.W. (1989). Lecciones de Estética. Madrid, Akal

KOSUTH, Joseph. (1969). Elarte después de la filosofía, [on line],Disponible en http://artecontempo.blogspot.com/2005/09/joseph-kosuth.html,consulta realiza el 12 de octubre de 2009.

MARGOLIS, Joseph. (1960). “Aesthetic perception”, The journal ofaesthetics and art criticism, Vol.19, No.2 (Winter), pp.209-213

MARGOLIS, Joseph. (1961). “Describing and interpreting works of art”,Philosophy and phenomenological research, Vol.21, No.4 (Jun.), pp.537-542.

OREN, Michel. (1993). “Anti-Art as the end of cultural history”,Performing Arts Journal, Vol.15, No.2 (Mayo), pp.1-30

QUINE, W.V. (2002): Relatividad Ontológica y otros ensayos. Madrid,Tecnos.

THOMASSON, Amie L. (2005). “The ontology of art and knowledge inaesthetics”, The journal of aesthetics and art criticism, Vol.63/No.3(Summer), pp.221-229

VÁSQUEZ ROCCA, Adolfo. (2007). “Joseph Beuys “Cada hombre, unartista”; Los Documenta de Kassel o el arte abandona la galería”, Psikeba:Revista de Psicoanálisis y Estudios Culturales. No.6.

Downloads

Download data is not yet available.

Similar Articles

1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 > >> 

You may also start an advanced similarity search for this article.